Abortion on Demand is the only Defensible Libertarian Position

In a recent Ron Paul CNN interview with Piers Morgan, Paul tried to wiggle out of the “pro-life” moral quandary of denying legal protection to the zygote in the instance of rape(“honest rape,” as he qualified it) by appealing to a supposed equivalent moral quandary of the abortion on demand position regarding the distinction between terminating a mature fetus vs killing a new born infant. However, contra Paul, the latter is not a moral quandary; but the former pro-life position very much is.

Pro-life, by definition, implies pacifism. While pacifism certainly is a legitimate moral foundation to hold, its moral constraints are unenforceable. It’s enforcement, by its own standard, would be a moral violation. For example, it’s one thing to voluntarily deny your own moral claim to self-defense but it’s quite another to involuntarily enforce this moral claim against other agents. The enforcement of the pacifist moral constraint would necessarily violate the pacifist constraint. The exemption of an enforcer from the moral constraint it is enforcing is a primary libertarian complaint against the nature of the State itself. Any enforcement model that exhibits such characteristics bears an unlibertarian classification.

Paul is often quoted as saying “you can’t protect liberty without protecting life.” But this is nonsense. You can’t protect life, that is, enforce violations against it, without enforceable moral constraints. Life qua life, which is equivalent to the “sanctity of life,” is a pacifist position. But the pacifist position, as noted above, is unenforceable. Given this, we certainly can apply a libertarian test or criterion to the moral constraints that are necessarily enforced.

In reality, the pro-lfe position rarely is pro-life, i.e., pacifist. Life qua life, or the sanctity of life position, is narrowly applied to pregnancy(although typically extended to euthanasia as well). Outside of this limited scope, however, the right of self-defense re-emerges, evidenced by the strong correlation of the “pro-life” position with a “pro gun rights” position. Some, however, like Paul, makes exceptions for rape and threats to the mother’s life. But these exceptions violate the sanctity of life constraint. Here the exceptions disprove the rule. Hence the moral quandary.

Now the problem of enforceability of obligated pacifism doesn’t disappear because of an arbitrary narrowing of applicability–in this case, to pregnancy. Those who impose an obligation of pacifism without exceptions for pregnancy encounter an obvious moral quandary, namely the problem of spontaneous abortion. This is not a trivial side consideration. Spontaneous abortions occur at roughly the same order of magnitude as surgical(and/or chemical) abortions. To differentiate between the two using “intent” as the criterion ad hoc redefines intent as the only criterion in legal jurisprudence. And we can definitively link the probability of spontaneous abortion to a female’s age. So to use an analogy: if a driver accidentally hit and killed a child in a school zone while driving 25mph, that driver might escape criminal sanction. However, if the driver was driving 100mph and hit/killed a child, and, say, this was the driver’s third time killing a child in a school zone driving at such a speed, it would be very unlikely that said driver would escape criminal culpability.

The above analogy applies to females over certain age, say, 35, who repeatedly attempt pregnancy. This problem has spawned an entire industry of “assisted reproduction technologies.” However, under a pacifist obligation, this industry would have to be banned. Analogous to the idea of restricted speed zones around schools(children), a pacifist obligation would require an upper age restriction for pregnancy eligibility. This is unenforceable sans age-mandatory tubal ligation.

The no-exception pro-life position(the majority of them, at least) is not about to go this far. Hence the exception to the rule and the moral quandary. The more general point that being made is that, actuarially speaking, pregnancy is a risky proposition, both for the female and the pre-natal entity(even excluding surgical abortions, only 75% of pregnancies result in live births). A moral obligation of pacifism to enforce life qua life vis a vis pregnancy would necessarily criminalize it in a totalitarian sense. In a practical sense, what the pro-life position really reduces to is an arbitrary enforcement of a moral offense against female sexual freedom.

Given the moral quandary of the pro-life position, which is unresolvable, a frequent defense is to switch gears and cast abortion on demand as suffering from its own quandary. This is typically expressed by stating that abortion on demand implies legitimizing infanticide. I would actually claim the opposite: that abortion on demand legitimizes obligation on the part of the parent post-birth. How is this?

The abortion on demand position suffers no moral quandary because it imposes no moral constraint on the female’s contractual freedom to terminate a pregnancy, unless such a constraint has been contractually/voluntarily agreed to. Because of the absence of any pacifist obligation regarding pregnancy, the act of carrying the pre-natal entity to term implicitly imposes an obligation on the part of the parent post-birth which arguably resolves a moral contractarian problem vis a vis parental moral constraints regarding children(which are incapable of contracting).From a moral contractarian position, abortion on demand is at least a necessary condition(although perhaps not a sufficient condition) for parental obligation.

Even if we drop the moral contractarian perspective, we still have a standard libertarian constraint that necessarily must frown on impersonal pacifist obligations. As explained above, it is an obvious moral quandary to impose an obligation to carry “conception” to “live birth.” If we redefine the obligation to say the that obligation starts at the point of “viability,” that is, the obligation is to carry a viable fetus to term, then we are talking about a moral constraint against “third trimester” abortions. Of course, practically speaking, we are only talking about 2% of the total number of per annum surgical abortions. These are almost always cases of health complications. And it is also roughly at this point that the hard choices between a healthy female and an unhealthy fetus become clear. The “viability” constraint, in practical terms, has little consequence in terms its expressed intent, which would be the “protection” of life, and quite a bit of potential consequence in terms pacifist obligations imposed on the female regarding her own health and her moral calculation regarding her own health relative to that of the “viable fetus.” The latter moral calculation may indeed be a moral quandary for the female in terms of individual choice, but it only becomes a moral quandary in terms of enforceable obligations if we define it as a duty to be enforced one way or another. So to be concrete, a mandatory viability test could be used to deny permission to terminate a pregnancy but it also could be used to deny permission to carry to term based on some risk assessment model. Those who favor the former application of a “viability test” are likely to be horrified by the latter application example. But to legitimize the former legitimizes the latter. It’s a bit arbitrarily narrow to refer to a viability standard(as an enforceable obligation to deny the female the moral calculation to terminate a pregnancy) but to nonetheless give absolute freedom to the female to carry to term regardless of the risks to herself. The other side of the equation is bound to become a point of consideration when you socialize “viability standards.” The only way to avoid the moral quandaries of enforcement is to drop the enforceable constraints and leave the moral quandaries up to individual conscience.

Conclusion

Abortion is often presented as a difficult problem. While I will concede that abortion may present moral quandaries to individual conscience, I nonetheless find no difficulty in staking out the only defensible libertarian position regarding its enforceable moral constraints: none. Any such enforceable constraint results in moral quandaries that simply cannot be enforced without arbitrary exemptions to save the enforcement regime from becoming a total criminalization of pregnancy. Interestingly, those who typically defend prohibition of abortion on the grounds that it is necessary to defend civilization end up criminalizing, in a totalitarian sense, the very foundation of it: human reproduction. The only way for the prohibitionists to avoid this dilemma is to take the position that “abortion is murder, except when it’s not.”

Because the abortion on demand position imposes no moral or pacifist constraints on pregnancy, it avoids the aforementioned moral quandaries of enforcement. However, some will charge that AoD provides a moral foundation for infanticide. The charge here would be that “birth” is an arbitrary dividing line and that AoD suffers from its own exemption: “killing children is murder, except when its not.” On one hand I have to concede children are part of the difficult problem of libertarianism regarding enforceable obligations(defined by contract). Indeed, Benjamin Tucker is noted for defining children as property until the point of contract. But the problem of the inability to contract(or lack of contractual agreement) extends beyond children. For example, what are our obligations to animals? To strangers? I readily admit that Tucker’s position is a moral quandary that shouldn’t be left up to individual conscience, but the only path I see to an implied enforceable obligation with respect to children is one that passes through no pacifist obligation of pregnancy. I certainly don’t think a pacifist obligation attached to pregnancy resolves this problem. On the contrary this merely transfers the ownership title over to the State. I don’t see any scourge of infanticide occurring. But I do see an ever encroaching problem developing of children more or less becoming property of the State.

6 thoughts on “Abortion on Demand is the only Defensible Libertarian Position

  1. If I may…

    We libertarians hold that all power arises from the people, thus when two people voluntarily act in a manner which can be expected to produce a new life, ought we not to conclude that a new life has been created when pregnancy occurs? Else, what of our axiomatic contention?

    Now, if one party or the other was not acting voluntarily, it is plain that no life has been created. The simple method for sieving the two situations is to look for a criminal complaint. Involuntary sex is rape. No complaint, no rape.

    Every abortion ought to be accompanied by a criminal complaint against the person(s) responsible for the involuntary pregnancy. No complaint, no abortion.

    1. Thanx for the comment…

      We conclude that the new life occurs when the new life occurs. Empirically, this has nothing to do with intent. Part of my post addressed this type of argument–using “intent” in an ad hoc way regarding enforceable obligations.

      Practically speaking, if people have sex with the intent of having children, then usually no abortion will follow unless circumstances dramatically change. of course, not everyone has sex for the purpose of producing offspring.

      To re-summarize my argument:

      Abortion may be a matter of individual conscience, but you can’t enforce any obligation to carry to term without criminalizing reproduction in a totalitarian sense–unless you make ad hoc, arbitrary exemptions. Exemptions, in terms of enforceable obligations, that would never apply outside of the abortion context. The only position that does not suffer from these enforceable moral quandries is abortion on demand.

      Cheers…

    2. “We libertarians hold that all power arises from the people, thus when two people voluntarily act in a manner which can be expected to produce a new life, ought we not to conclude that a new life has been created when pregnancy occurs?”

      Um, no.

      “Else, what of our axiomatic contention?”

      It’s an independent matter.

      “Every abortion ought to be accompanied by a criminal complaint against the person(s) responsible for the involuntary pregnancy. No complaint, no abortion.”

      And what agency prevents it in the absence of said complaint? You’re not really a libertarian, are you.

      And it’s quite amusing how you guys/sophists treat this as if it were completely symmetric between the two people.

  2. While I agree with the position about abortion on demand, there is the alternative position for the life of the fetus.

    And, like everything else in terms of true liberty, it is up to those who wish to “do something” to do it.

    When someone is stranded on the highway, they are helped by those who wish to help. Same for a fetus.

    Let the people who want to “save the life” do so. Let them have the fetus. Let them fund alternative methods of abortion, let them invent ways to accomplish what they wish to accomplish.

    But just like someone stranded on the side of the road, those who just drive on by cannot be held responsible for NOT trying to save the fetus.

    —-

    Want something really controversial? How about male abortion? If a woman gets pregnant and she doesn’t want to be, she gets the choice. The man involved has just as much right to not be “pregnant”, to get the choice.

    Yet when that is brought up, the same bunch who demand the woman have a right to choose turn around and demand that “the man take responsibility for his actions”.

    Try it, see what kind of reactions you get.

    1. Thanx for the comment

      I agree on both your points. (1) yes, people should be free to market an alternative. of course, the alternative should not be “forced” on anyone. Here, i’m referring specifically to, say, Block’s “evacuation.”

      (2) yes, it should be implied that if the female has no enforceable obligation, then neither does the male. I’m not sure how anyone could make such a claim with a straight face. Otherwise, its an argument that relies on a “special exemption,” a type of flawed argument that sows the seeds of the other side of the “special exemption” argument, the type I have attacked in my post–that is applied to restrict AoD.

      Cheers…

    2. “Want something really controversial? How about male abortion? If a woman gets pregnant and she doesn’t want to be, she gets the choice. The man involved has just as much right to not be “pregnant”, to get the choice.

      Yet when that is brought up, the same bunch who demand the woman have a right to choose turn around and demand that “the man take responsibility for his actions”.

      Try it, see what kind of reactions you get.”

      My reaction is that it is hard to be less intellectually honest than this absurd pretense that the man and woman are equivalently situated.

      Reply

Leave a reply to Bob Robertson Cancel reply