The Social Justice of a Police State

The Social Justice of a Police State

Fareed Zakaria recently published a piece, Incarceration Nation, that points out there are now more people under ‘correctional supervision’ in America – more than 6 million – than were in the Soviet Gulag Archipelago at its height. The imprisonment rate in the US is approaching 1 per 100 which is generally an order of magnitude greater than the other western-styled democracies around the globe. Zakaria notes that this gap between the US and the rest of the world is relatively recent phenomenon. Thirty years ago, at the start of the so-called “Reagan Revolution,” the US incarceration rate, though at the outer bounds, was nonetheless in line with other civilized democracies. Since then, however, the US incarceration rate has more than quintupled.

I mention the Zakaria article because it offers a relevant contextual backdrop to this recent Cato Unbound essay, A Bleeding Heart History of Libertarianism, by Matt Zwolinski and John Tomasi. Both of these authors are academics involved in the so-called “Bleeding Heart Libertarian Project” to marry distributive justice to libertarian political theory. The preferrred distributive justice paradigm is the Rawlsian one. The intent of their essay is to demonstrate the compatiblity of this paradigm with a historical weaving of the (classical) liberal tradition. The corollary is that libertarianism, as typically defined, is a departure from this tradition. It is proposed then that a sympathetic adaptation of Rawls will right the course of a proper libertarian political theory.

Frankly, I would not dispute the primary thrust of the essay: that a “non-bleeding heart libertarianism” is a departure from liberalism. I would qualify this agreement by noting that a “non-bleeding heart libertarianism” is not a modern development. Historically, libertarianism is rooted in a rejection of any normative social contract rationale for obedience to the State. Of course, we are talking about a different history than the highly selective one outlined by Zwolinski and Tomasi. However, it is not my intention to adjudicate libertarian history in this post. I’ve previously given my account of this history here and here. Instead, I will only point out there is a reason why libertarianism departs from liberalism: namely, because liberalism inherently violates its own constraints regarding the artificiality of the State and politics. By artificiality, we mean the State is not supposed to become the source of government. At the very least, the State should avoid the evolutionary equilibrium of becoming the total source of government(i.e., a Police State). However, Zwolinski and Tomasi’s essay demonstrates how easily distributive justice can legitimize a police state and provides yet another example of bleeding hearts not exactly bleeding for everyone.

The Zwolinski and Tomasi essay begins with an erroneous, straw-man premise:

To the extent that respect for property leaves some individuals poor and destitute, individuals might be called by a sense of charity and beneficence to respond. But the moral justification of free market institutions is logically independent from any claims about the effects of those institutions on the material holdings of the poor.

Whether intentionally or unintentionally, Zwolinski and Tomasi mischaracterize the libertarian principle. Enforceable moral claims of any property rights regime are not independent of the material holdings of agents. Indeed, the libertarian principle is actually a moral constraint against property rights regimes. If agents are worse off under the regime than they would be without the regime, then there is no moral obligation to obey the regime. This moral constraint illuminates an essential distinction between libertarians and progressives. Libertarians are not intererested in distributive justice correcting unjust regimes. The correction is the abolition of these regimes. I would argue the classical libertarian position–if we were to,say, follow Bastiat–is that any property rights regime that requires distributive justice to retain legitimacy is probably corrupt. Following Bastiat, we would identify distributive justice as a form of bribery against defection. I would add that these bribes are much more directed at the “middle class” than the so-called poor. Thus, we can expect the so-called “social safety net” to largely consist of an array of middle-class subsidies and not a device or thing designed to minimize a worst-case condition.

Zwolinski and Tomasi identify Rawlsian justice as the “gold standard” of contemporary social justice. But as I havepreviously discussed, Rawls later modified his methodological approach to defend his principles of justice. David Friedman, in his critique of Zwolinksi and Tomasi provides a clue to the problem with Rawls’ original approach. Writes Friedman:

And one implication of that version, taken as literally as I have been taking the natural rights alternative, is that it is better to have a world where everyone is at a utility level of a hundred than a world with one person at ninety-nine and everyone else at a thousand. I have never yet been able to figure out why anyone takes either the derivation or the conclusion seriously.

The answer to Friedman’s criticism is that Rawls’ formulation was actually challenged. In particular, John Harsanyi’s “originalist position” maximized aggregate utility(straight utilitarian). Indeed, Harsanyi’s version exposed the problem with the “Veil of Ignorance” as a normative construct: it lacked a plausible risk aversion model. Rawls’ “Maxmin” version is equivalent to infinite risk aversion. Harsanyi’s “max utilitarian” is equivalent to zero risk aversion. Neither infinite nor zero risk aversion is plausible. The VOI instrument has to establish the appropriate level of risk aversion in the original position that falls somewhere between zero and infinity. Obviously, then, the VOI does not yield unique solutions and thus loses its normative power.

Friedman’s primary criticism of Zwolinski and Tomasi is that the Rawlsian conception doesn’t actually link to the historical utilitarian foundations of “classical liberalism.” But John Harsanyi’s formulation directly casts the Originalist Position in such utilitarian terms. And it is this utilitarian casting which more or less demonstrated that the normative foundation of Rawls’ theory was built over a house of cards.

Rawl’s modified approach to his theory of justice was developed in his later book, “Political Liberalism.” Political Liberalism more or less concedes the lack of a rational foundation for a unanimity regarding hypothetical justice principles. Political liberalism is an explicit shift from the rational to the “reasonable,” a shift from justice as “moral” to justice as “political.” It is here that Rawls lays out the ideas of the “overlapping consensus” and “Public Reason.” The government stays neutral between competing moral foundations. Justice is a “political product” defined by the overlapping consensus of moral dialogue. Reasonable discussion is supposed to validate Rawls’ principles of justice. In practice, however, it merely roots justice in the cultural war. So, the gold standard of contemporary social justice turns out to be the overlapping consensus between Rush Limbaugh and Daily Kos. This, of course, is a farce. But it only points out the inherent flaw of “Public Reason.” Public Reason has nothing to with liberal justice; instead it is entirely rooted in a communitarian war over “recognition.”

The Zwolinski/Tomasi essay makes it clear that “recognition” plays an important in who “qualifies” for justice. They propose a rather high barrier of entry to qualify for being “poor.” Evidently, “Poor” excludes the social rift-raft and the unemployed. To be properly poor means to be employed. But this is a silly and obviously artificial exclusionary construction. An obvious solution to maximize the condition of our properly defined “poor” would be to simply to maximize the barrier of entry to qualify to work. A “social justice claim” reduces to a protectionist claim, which is often the case. This type of protectionism becomes particularly insidious when you consider that who is legally “recognized” to work in a National Security State becomes a matter of public debate of an overlapping consensus between Rush Limbaugh and Daily Kos. This is hardly justice; rather, it’s a moral perversion.

In the past I have discussed the concept of the “Pink Police State.” The Pink Police State, like all police states, delineates a clear demarcation of privilege between the professional classes and those who are shit out of luck in terms of inclusion in the club. In other words, it is “the illegals,” the scapegoats, and the “unrecognized” who take the full brunt of a police state. It breeds a permanent underclass. The Pink Police State, however, is a type of classification that likely portends a flourishing recognition of a “libertarian” professional class. This professional class will spare no opportunity to equate unprecedented recognition with an unprecedented condition of human liberty. And the primary aim of this community will be recognition, not justice(or reform). In this vein, the Bleeding Heart Libertarian Project simply appears to be an exercise in professional recognition. It is difficult to take seriously claims of distributive justice in a police state, particularly if the “bleeding heart” concern for the poor excludes the very victims of this police state. But this is exactly how a professional class can babble about social justice in an underlying context marked by an unprecedented political economy of a prison industrial complex.

The West is accustomed to regarding “Police States” as restricted to non-democratic states, but “voting” has nothing to do with its definition. The definition is as follows: (1) undue restrictions on the freedom of mobility, the freedom of transactions, the freedom to work (2) perverse rates of domestic incarceration (3) system-wide domestic surveillance organs engaged in domestic spying in all aspects of the social, economic and political life of its citizens. The makeup of these organs will usually entail some degree of a secret police and an unaccountable intelligence complex (4) the militarization of the borders (5) an arbitrary distinction between law and the exercise of power by the executive agency (6) a militarization or para-militarization of “law enforcement” (7) a social context where the government actively propagandizes a permanent enemy, a permanent threat, a permanent war (8) a social context that glorifies the organs of authority, “the men and women in uniform.”

The United States is a Police State. And the Pink Police State that will be its social justice…

5 thoughts on “The Social Justice of a Police State

  1. Great post. Just one quibble: I’d want to distinguish between defining BHL as “a version of libertarianism that accepts social justice” and defining it as “a version of libertarianism that accepts a specifically (neo-)Rawlsian form of social justice.” By the first definition, I’m a BHL; by the second I’m not. And the first definition is the official one; that’s why Gary Chartier and I are BHL blog members and Charles Johnson was a visiting BHL blog member. The neo-Rawlsian approach represented by Matt Zwolinski and John Tomasi and Kevin Vallier is another species of BHL; it’s not equivalent to the whole genus.

  2. “Harsanyi’s “max utilitarian” is equivalent to zero risk aversion. ”

    Von Neumann solved that problem quite a long time ago. You simply incorporate risk aversion into the utility function–it’s equivalent to declining marginal utility of income. If we use Von Neumann utility, Harsanyi’s argument goes through whatever level of risk aversion people have. And that’s consistent with previous ideas of utility, since there is no reason why a utilitarian should assume that utility is linear in income.

    I thought of mentioning Harsanyi in my piece, but didn’t think it necessary, since my point was that Rawls’ argument doesn’t work, not that a more plausible version leads to utilitarianism.

    Incidentally, it leads to maximizing average utility, not, as you said, aggregate utility.

    1. Welcome. Thanx for the comment(and the correction🙂 )

      Forgive my error regarding aggregate v. avg in terms of utility maximization, but my point was that it was a utilitarian argument regarding the originalist position that, in part, prompted Rawls to later resort to Public Reason to validate his two principles of justice. I tend to get exacerbated with those–e.g., Zwolinski/Tomasi–who talk about the originalist position in normative terms without addressing the fact that even Rawls abandoned that effort. The gold standard of social justice turns out to be political consensus, which I think is more like a “lead standard.”

      By the way,since you took time to comment on this post that involved you in the discussion, perhaps you can address my earlier critique of your position regarding libertarianism and class theory(in your critique of Roderick Long). Here:
      https://rulingclass.wordpress.com/2011/03/31/the-matrix-as-ruling-class/

      The problem: The rational choice model of treating government like a market suffers from an empirical problem of outlays being substantially smaller than rents. It appears to be a rigged market which implies a degree of self-preservation that you dismissed in Machinery of Freedom. In short, the empirical evidence tends to demonstrate that rent seeking can become the source of the decision-making rules(constitutional constraints). In terms of Tullock and Buchanan, we could say that rent-seeking results in the union of the protective and redistributive state.

      Cheers…

  3. Thanx for the comment.

    My one quibble with your above taxonomy is that you are essentially posing a “version of libertarianism that accepts social justice” versus a “version that accepts distributive justice;” of course, social justice, commonly understood, means distributive justice(or some form of it). So, you are, in a sense, attempting to redefine the meaning of the term(to exclude distributive justice). But this seems a bit of a pointless exercise given that the identifiable usage of the term(one that equates it with distributive justice) extends well beyond the libertarian sphere. Put differently, the BHL project can more or less be recast as argument over whether social justice should mean distributive justice. This is all fine and dandy but it hardly points to a relevant outcome. To use an analogy closer to your professional field, it’s akin to quibbling nominalist factions, say “constructivist mathematicians,” agreeing on a definition of “a set” in order to reproduce (some) mathematical theorems and expecting “the realists” to embrace the nominalist’s definition of a set.

    I would say the relevant problem in libertarianism is the “redistribution problem.” This problem: a transition from unjust system A to a new system X, one that could be defined as capable of enforcing just outcomes, cannot occur without redistributing away a sufficient degree of advantages accumulated in A. This “redistribution” must occur in A, otherwise X will be just as bad as A. From social/economic sciences we can probably identify a sufficient condition(using, say, Coase’s theorem) regarding the eradication of bargaining advantages that would otherwise impose high transaction costs for overcoming poorly defined property rights. As transaction costs –> 0, the initial allocation of property rights doesn’t matter. So, in this sense, the redistribution problem would be more about transaction costs than an egalitarian re-distribution of property. The later smacks too much of a “dictatorship of this or that” and probably can be shown to be neither a necessary nor sufficient condition for X.

    I think the pertinent critique of modern libertarianism is that it doesn’t address the “redistribution problem.” Nozick sort of did in ASU, but his take was more of a gigantic restitution in A, though remaining in A. The redistribution problem is A –> X. Frankly, I don’t think you can seriously talk about a libertarian social theory without addressing the “redistribution problem.”

    But the redistribution problem is not “social justice.” It is not distributive justice. Distributive Justice is simply compensation for ongoing injustice without correction. It’s a bribe. It’s akin to every morning waking up and having a bully beat your face in. The beatings never stop, but if you are lucky, you’ll get a monthly check for your pain and suffering(distributive justice is also different from restitution, since the latter is a correction, a condition where no futher injustice exists). Distributive Justice works within in A and simply compensates(or bribes) for the ongoing injustice of A.

    My critique of Zwolinski/Tomasi is that they talk incessently about social justice ostensibly being a thing to compensate the “marginalized,” but their definiton of the poor actually excludes the marginalized. It smacks as an exercise in professional academic signaling. My crique was actually from a liberal standpoint and not really from a libertarian one.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s